DR. STANLEY KRIPPNER

PSIONA Index PSI  RESEARCH EMERGENT MIND HEARTSTRINGS MRU 2007 OAK, Inc. JOHN GOWAN ASKLEPIA KRIPPNER NEXUS ZINE PSI OPS TEAM CHAOSOPHY MULTIVERSE HYPNOSIS  PSI Links MANIFESTO 06 Holographic Nonlocal Mind Whole Sum MC4Dummies Blog Archive Links Photo 2

Dr. Stanley Krippner, PhD


Stan Krippner first caught the public imagination with the publication of his groundbreaking work DREAM TELEPATHY, Experiments in Nocturnal ESP (1973). He went on to do equally innovative holistic research in shamanism, consciousness, healing, creativity, extraordinary human potential, and human sexuality. This pioneer of parapsychology has travelled to every shamanic corner of the globe, mentored many, including myself, and brought the mystifying world back into the arena of general psychology, rather than a marginalized specialty.

Stan and I served together on the Asklepia Board, and spoke together for the first Chaos Conference, 1992, but our acquaintance goes back decades. He published Rick Miller's HOLOGRAPHIC CONCEPT OF REALITY. This paper was presented at the First International Congress of Psychotronics, Prague, 1973. First printing was in the journal Psychoenergetic Systems, ed. Stanley Krippner, Vol.1, 1975. 55-62. Gordon & Breach Science Publishers Ltd., Great Britain. Reprinted in the book PSYCHOENERGETIC SYSTEMS, S. Krippner, editor. c1979. 231-237. Gordon & Breach, New York, London, Paris.



Stanley Krippner, Ph.D., is professor of psychology at Saybrook Graduate School in San Francisco where he designed many of the courses in the consciousness/spirituality concentration. At Saybrook, he has supervised dissertation research projects for dozens of students. He holds faculty appointments at the Universidade Holistica Internacional (Brasilia) and the instituto de Medicina y Tecnologia Avanzada de la Conducta (Ciudad Juarez, Mexico) where he helped create the certificate programs in human sexuality and in rational-emotive behavior therapy.

Over the years, Dr. Krippner has conducted workshops and seminars on personal mythology, dreams, hypnosis, and/or anomalous phenomena in Argentina, Brazil, Canada, Colombia, Cuba, Cyprus, Ecuador, Finland, France, Germany, Great Britain, Italy, Japan, Mexico, the Netherlands, Panama, the Philippines, Portugal, Puerto Rico, Russia, South Africa, Spain, Sweden, Venezuela, and at several congresses of the Interamerican Psychological Association. He is a member of the advisory board for the International School for Psychotherapy, Counseling, and Group Leadership (St. Petersburg) and has given invited addresses for the Chinese Academy of Sciences, the Russian Academy of Pedagogical Sciences, and the Artigas Foreign Service Institute in Montevideo, Uruguay.

In 2002, making his ninth trip to Russia to attend the Tenth Annual international Conference on Conflict Resolution, Dr. Krippner spoke on children’s nightmares as a sequelae to wartime trauma. This is one of several topics dealt with in his book The Psychological Effects of War on Civilians: An International Perspective, co-edited with Teresa Mcintyre. The Special Collections at the Kent State University Library houses Dr. Krippner’s archives, over one thousand books, monographs, articles, chapters, and book reviews in English and a dozen non-English languages.

*************************
The Epistemology and Technologies of Shamanic States of Consciousness
Stanley Krippner, Ph.D., Saybrook Graduate School

ABSTRACT: Shamanism can be described as a group of techniques by which its practitioners enter the "spirit world," purportedly obtaining information that is used to help and to heal members of their social group. The shamans' epistemology, or ways on knowing, depended on deliberately altering their conscious state and/or heightening their perception to contact spiritual entities in "upper worlds," "lower worlds," and "middle earth" (i.e., ordinary reality). For the shaman, the totality of inner and outer reality was fundamentally an immense signal system, and shamanic states of consciousness were the first steps toward deciphering this signal system. Homo sapiens sapiens was probably unique among early humans in the ability to symbolize, mythologize, and, eventually, to shamanize. This species' eventual domination may have been due to its ability to take sensorimotor activity and use it as a bridge to produce narratives that facilitated human survival. Shamanic technologies, essential for the production and performance of myths and other narratives, interacted with shamanic epistemology, reinforcing its basic assumptions about reality.

*********************
THE CIRCLE OF SEX IN MYTHOLOGY AND FOLKLORE

Stanley Krippner, Ph.D.

ABSTRACT: According to Gavin Arthur’s “circle of sex” model, all humans fall on a continuum that allows for fluctuation in sexual disposition as well as the intensity of sexual activity. His typology of human sexual behavior avoids such pejorative labels as “abnormal,” “deviant,” and “pathological,” and introduces the terms “heterogenic,” “homogenic,” and “ambigenic” because such terms as “heterosexual” incorrectly combine Greek and Anglo-Saxon roots. Arthur illustrates his model with historical characters; or example, George V of England, the faithful husband of Queen Mary, fell at 12 noon, but Julius Caesar, known in his day as “every woman’s husband and every man’s wife,” fell into the “ambigenic category.” Sappho, the poet who lived on the island of Lesbos, was described as “three quarters homogenic” because, although she preferred Lesbian girls, she occasionally dallied with young shepherds. The writer Gertrude Stein was categorized as “homogenic” at 10 o’clock. Arthur denoted sexual intensity by putting someone in the sphere’s tropical center. Someone who has taken religious orders, however, might find himself or herself near the chilly regions of the circle. A Roman Catholic nun, who considers herself “married to Christ,” could be a 6 o’clock “heterogene." The psychiatrist, Jean Bolen, developed a model that paid special attention to the sexuality of the Greek gods and goddesses. But instead of using their sexuality as the basis for a typology as Arthur did, Bolen focused upon the deities as representing “archetypes,” “powerful inner patterns that allegedly shape behavior and influence emotions. In other words, there can be gay Ares types and lesbian Aphrodites because the archetypes they represent are broader than sexual preference. This typology may be more useful to psychotherapists than Arthur’s ingenious “circle of sex.”


Krippner and Hoffman

Graywolf, Iona, Stan

Sample Photo 2

Krippner and Hoffman

Sample Photo 3

Brief Description

Sample Photo 4

Krippner

Sample Photo 5

Iona and Stanley

Sample Photo 6

Brief Description

THE DREAMING BRAIN


Self-Organization in the Dreaming Brain
Stanley Krippner
Saybrook Graduate School and Research Center

Allan Combs
Department of Psychology CPO #1960
University of North Carolina at Asheville
Self-Organization in the Dreaming Brain
Abstract

This paper approaches dreaming consciousness through an examination of the self-organizing properties of the sleeping brain.

This view offers a step towards reconciliation between brain-based and content-based attempts to understand the nature of dreaming. Here it is argued that the brain can be understood as a complex self-organizing system that in dreaming responds to subtle influences such as residual feelings and memories. The hyper-responsiveness of the brain during dreaming is viewed in terms of the tendency of complex chaotic-like systems to respond to small variations in initial conditions (the butterfly effect) and to the amplification of subtle emotional and cognitive signals through the mechanism of stochastic resonance, all in combination with psychophysiological changes in the brain during both slow wave sleep and REM sleep dreaming. Such changes include the active inhibition of extroceptive stimulation and, especially in REM sleep, alterations in the brain’s dominant neuromodulatory systems, bombardment of the visual cortex with bursts of PGO activity, increases in limbic system activity, and a reduction of activity in the prefrontal regions.

Key words: brain, consciousness, dream, self-organization, REM sleep

Sleep affords the opportunity, within certain limits, for the brain to act of itself, and dreams are the result. Edward Clarke, A Study of False Sight; 1878

There have been a variety of recent theoretical approaches to the process of dreaming. These have emphasized the cognitive aspects of dreaming (e.g., Bosinelli, 1995; Foulkes, 1985, 1999; Moffitt, 1995), the underlying psychophysiological processes (e.g., Hobson and McCarley, 1977; Hobson, Pace-Schott, and Stickgold, 2000), the neurological substrate (Jouvet,
1999) combined with psychoanalytical considerations (Solms, 1997, 1999; Ullman, 1999), as well as connectionist (Globus, 1989; Hartmann, 1999) and neural network (e.g., Antrobus, 1990, 1991; Crick and Michison, 1986; Fookson and Antrobus, 1992) models for understanding the dreaming brain. The present paper combines the psychophysiological approach with the connectionist and neural network models, leading to considerations about the cognitive structure of dreams. It views the dreaming brain in terms of dynamical neurological processes that are most accurately described as chaotic (e.g., Arden, 1996; Screenivason, Pradhan, and Rapp, 1999).

Dreaming in REM Sleep

Much research on the dreaming brain pertains specifically to REM sleep. There are two reasons for this. The first is the misconception that dreams occur only in this state. The second is that since awakenings from REM sleep are more likely to be associated with dream recall, as much as ten times more likely according to Foulkes (1962)REM itself has become a widely accepted signal that dreaming is taking place. Thus, in laboratory and clinical settings there is often an ipso facto association between REM sleep and dreaming.

The reason why dreams occur more frequently during REM sleep is not well understood, but it is evident that during the REM state the brain is especially disposed to dreaming. For one thing, however, the brain actively inhibits extroceptive sensory input during REM sleep, and also blocks motor output from the higher centers of the brain (Mountcastle, 1974). Only those motor commands that are sent to the extremities, that is, to the fingers and toes, ordinarily get through, as do those sent to the eyes. The latter results in the rapid eye movements for which REM sleep was named. There is no question that REMs occasionally follow dream gazes (Herman, 1992), though it is doubtful that they usually do (but see Antrobus, 1990). In fact, their presence is highly correlated with bursts (or "waves") of large and seemingly randomly timed “spikes” of neuronal activity which originate in the pons of the lower brainstem and travel upward to the lateral geniculate bodies, from where they proceed on to the primary visual cortex.

These pontine-geniculate-occipital (PGO) waves play an important role in the widely respected activation-synthesis hypothesis, originally proposed by Allan Hobson and his research group in 1977 (e.g., Hobson and McCarley, 1977). It stated that the arrival of this irregular PGO activity at the occipital lobe serves as a powerful unstructured stimulus in which the sleeping brain seeks meaning, finding it in the creation of the images that we experience as dreams. Since its original publication Hobson’s theory has undergone a series of revisions (Hobson, Pace-Schott, Stickgold, and Kahn, 1998; Kahn, Pace-Schott, and Hobson, 1997).

The theory has retained its original form while honing its physiological accuracy and expanding its reach toward a general theory of conscious states and the brain. The present form of the theory is abbreviated as AIM, referring to the activation level of the brain in wakefulness, REM, and NREM sleep, the source of the information that the brain processes (external or internal), and the chemical modulation (aminergic or cholinergic) of the brain (Hobson, Pace-Schott, and Stickgold, 2000).

Hobson’s theory has in its favor that the timing of PGO waves is irregular, and globally (though not precisely) correlated with REM activity. It also helps put into perspective the fact that animals compensate for lost PGO activity to a greater degree than they do for lost REM time (Dement, Ferguson, Cohn, and Barchas, 1969). And at least one "primitive" mammal, the echidna (spiny anteater), exhibits periods of PGO activity in the brainstem during sleep while showing no REM whatsoever (Finkbeiner, 1998).

The theory is not, however, without difficulties. From a physiological point of view, it elevates diffuse cortical stimulation from the brainstem to the status of optical sensory input (Vogel, 1978). This inconsistency is especially problematic if Foulkes’ (1999) contention turns out to be true that infants who exhibit a great deal of REM sleep, in fact hardly dream at all (but see Hobson, Pace-Schott, and Stickgold, 2000, for a considered counter-argument). From the psychological point of view Hobson’s approach puts dream activity under the control of seemingly random PGO bombardment arising from the oldest and lowest levels of the brain.

Hobson, however, has not pursued a relentless reductionism. In 1993 he and his colleague David Kahn published an exploration of the idea that dream experiences are in part a product of self-organizing tendencies in the brain during REM sleep (Kahn and Hobson, 1993). This paper moved beyond the notion of dreams as random brain events, but did not yet articulate the actual formative processes that might underlie dreaming. Recently the present authors have worked with Kahn to develop a more detailed understanding of the brain’s dream process, one that spans the traditional chasm between the neurobiology of dreaming and the study of the content of dreams (Kahn, Combs, and Krippner, 1998).

The Self-Organized Brain in REM Dreaming

The basic idea in Kahn, Combs, and Krippner’s papers is that the dreaming brain “relaxes” into natural patterns of self-organized activity, which often reflect the residual moods, stresses, and concerns of waking life. To understand this, recall that during dreaming the brain is immersed in something like a sensory isolation tank and cut off from the influences of external sensory input. In this situation patterns of brain activity can relax into forms that are dependent primarily upon internal conditions (e.g., Antrobus, 1990). Consider, for instance, what happens when sand is dropped onto a vibrating surface like a drumhead or orchestral symbol. It dances about forming complex patterns characteristic of the physical dynamics of the vibrating surface beneath. Such patterns have been used to study the resonance properties of instruments such as violins.

In chaos theory, the
In our view, the patterns of activity that unfold over time in the dreaming brain are experienced as the narratives, which play themselves out in dreams (Combs and Krippner, 1998). We suggest that while the conditions under which these patterns unfold are different than in the waking state, the fundamental principles that underlie their creation are the same. A beginning has been made in working these out for cognitive systems (Hardy, 1998; Kampis, 1991; Port and van Gelder, 1995; Tschacher and Dauwalder, 1999), for algorithmic systems (Goertzel, 1994, 2000), and in terms of the phenomenology of the mind (Combs, 1996, Combs and Krippner, 1998). The basic idea in each case concerns complex chaotic systems that contain multiple processes which interact with each other to create new processes. These in turn interact, and so on. Out of this complex soup of interactions emerge more or less stable configurations of processes that evolve in time.

There is considerable evidence to suggest that many brain processes might be understood in terms of such dynamics (Basar, 1990; Freeman and Barrie, 1994; Halaz, 1995; Jeong, Joung, and Kim, 1998; Pribram, 1995; Robertson and Combs, 1995; Screenivason, Pradhan, and Rapp, 1999). Of course, the evolving patterns of neuronal activity in the brain and the emerging contents of the dream need only have a formal relationship with each other. To go beyond this would bring us face to face with Chalmer’s (1995) “hard problem,” the difficulty in explaining the neurochemical basis for the qualia of consciousness. More to the point, we note that Haskell (1986) has convincingly argued that the appearance of seemingly random activity in the brain, as exemplified by PGO waves, does not preclude the operation of a systematic and fully functioning cognitive system. In the present paper we propose that the experiential elements of dreams, such as thoughts, perceptions, emotions, and memories, ride on underlying brain processes, which interact to elicit new experiential elements, and so one. During dreaming this process is both constrained and facilitated by the particular conditions of the dreaming brain.

Now, returning to the role played by PGO activity in the REM dreaming brain, we suggest that this activity sets the cortical system into motion and keeps it there. PGO discharges carry with them waves of powerful cholinergic stimulation to thecortex, keeping the brain on the move, and shaking it down again and again toward relaxed configurations. In line with this way of thinking, Mamelak and Hobson (1989) have suggested that PGO stimulation is tied to the high rate of narrative or plot shifts experienced during REM dreaming. Such shifts are significantly more frequent in REM dreaming than during dreaming reported from slow wave sleep (Cavallero, Cicogna, Natalie, Occhionero, and Zito, 1992; Foulkes, 1962), and may be essential to the “bizarreness” of REM dreams (Poret and Hobson, 1986).

One of the major contributions of Hobson and his group was the discovery that during REM sleep the brain shifts away from the widespread inhibition that characterizes waking activity because of the dominance of aminergic neurochemicals (serotonin and norepinepherine). With the onset of sleep the brain comes under the influence of the cholinergic neurochemical acetylcholine, which predisposes it to easy activation (Hobson, 1988, 1994).

In other words, activity in the REM dreaming brain is less viscous and more mercurial than in the waking brain, allowing it to move easily into residual patterns left by moods and concerns of waking life. Such fluidity would also enlarge the attractors through which brain activity flows, effectively allowing easier connections to be made between feelings, memories, and the products of the imagination, all of which is to say that dream experience is open to greater novelty than is waking experience. An idea similar to this is suggested by Hartmann (1999), who notes that during dreaming the neural networks that comprise the working circuitry of the brain seem less constrained by daytime reality and more open to novel connections. The extent of agreement between Hartmann’s approach and our own is witnessed by the fact that the formal analysis of activity patterns in complex neural networks such as those found in the brain are often carried out in terms of attractors.

Studies of Brain Activity During REM Sleep

Modern brain imaging studies are beginning to provide valuable insights into the nature of the REM sleeping brain. It turns out that one important aspect of REM sleep is a significant reduction in the activation of the prefrontal cortex (Braun, Balkin, Wesensten, Gwady, Carson, Varga, Baldwin, Belenky, and Herscovitch, 1998; Maquet, Peters, Aerts, Delfiore, Degueldre, Luxen, and Franck, 1996). This region of the brain is important for a number of higher mental abilities on which we rely during wakefulness. These include working memory, which is the ability to keep important facts in mind while carrying out a task. With a reduced working memory during dreaming it is not surprising that we find the abrupt transitions in plot and location less surprising during dreaming than we would in waking life. The idea of a state-specific amnesia for working memory during REM sleep is further supported by Hobson and his colleagues, who note that such amnesia is facilitated by a reduction of aminergic modulation in the brain by 50% in NREM sleep and nearly 100% in REM sleep (Hobson, 1988; Hobson and Steriade, 1986; Steriade and McCarley, 1990).

The prefrontal cortex also plays an important role in making plans for the future. People with damage to this area often seem listless and without direction, in part because they do not think about what lies ahead. In dreaming we likewise think little about the future, simply going along with the dream narrative without question (Hall and Van de Castle, 1966; Tonay, 1991). In this vein, there seems a significant attenuation of attention during dreaming (Hartmann, 1966), as well as a loss of self-reflection (Blagrove, 1996). In waking life the prefrontal lobe may also play an important role in maintaining a sense of self-identity, and particularly an ability for self-reflection. With these abilities “off-line” during dreaming (Blagrove, 1996) the dreamer has little
ability to reflect on the situation, or even notice the strangeness of events experienced.

Recently recorded images of the sleeping brain during REM show that in contrast to the prefrontal cortex, portions of the limbic system are highly active during REM sleep (Braun et al., 1998; Maquet et al., 1996). These structures are associated with emotion, which makes perfect sense given the fact that dreams are high in emotional content. The limbic system is far from well understood, however, and research continues to disclose new aspects of its operations. Carl Anderson (1998; Anderson and Mandell, 1996) at the Harvard Medical School, for instance, is currently exploring the idea that the right and left amygdaloid complexes of the limbic system are key structures for cataloging emotional memories, and that PGO activity shared between them in REM sleep helps balance the activation of such memories to keep the brain from getting stuck in particular attractor patterns such as depression or anxiety.

For interest’s sake we also mention that images of the sleeping brain during REM show increased activity in the anteriorcingulate cortex and the right parietal lobe, both associated with the regulation of attention (Braun et al., 1998). Contrary towhat would be expected from the original activation-synthesis hypothesis, there actually seems to be a lowered level of activity in the primary visual cortex of the occipital lobe compared to that seen during waking visual activity, but relatively robust activation of the adjacent (parastriate) regions. According to some researchers (Crick and Koch, 1995; Koch, 1998; Revonsuo, 1998) the latter are involved in the processing of visual images and are essential to the conscious experience of vision. Recently, Hobson has expanded his theory to include the importance of activity in the parastriate area in dream imagery (e.g., Hobson, Pace-Schott, and Stickgold, 2000).


REM and SWS Dreaming


At this point some accounting must be made of the fact that dream reports are often obtained following awakenings from NREM, or slow wave sleep (SWS). Though the likelihood of obtaining dream reports is lower for SWS than REM sleep, in fact such reports are associated with all stages of SWS (Foulkes, 1962). On the average they indicate less vividness and clarity of imagery (Antrobus, Hartwig, Rosa, Reisel, and Fein, 1987; Arkin, Antrobus, and Ellman, 1978) and fewer plot shifts (Cavallero et al., 1992; Foulkes, 1962) than REM associated reports, but the differences are usually small and not always reliable. Tracy and Tracy (1974), for example, reported dreams of high vividness from both light (stage 2) and deep (stage 4)SWS, casting doubt on the commonly held assumption that REM dreams are vivid because cortical activation is high during REM sleep. Interestingly, however, Hobson and his colleagues (Hobson, Pace-Schott, and Stickgold, 2000) as well as Nielsen (1999) have recently undertaken extensive re-analyses of REM and NREM dream studies reported throughout the literature, leading them to reaffirm the importance of differences in dream content between these two types of sleep. A thorough review of Hobson et al.’s analyses is beyond the scope of this article, but paramount among their considerations are concerns regarding memory deficiencies associated especially with REM sleep, and the statistical methods typically used to analyze dream reports.

The authors, for example, note that longer reports, with more words, often indicate greater bizarreness, though this fact is often obscured in their statistical treatment.

At the time of this writing, the issue of differences between REM and NREM dreaming is not settled. It would appear to the present writers, however, that differences do exist and that they are important. This means that, on average, the
characteristics of NREM dreams are somewhere between those of REM dreams and ordinary waking consciousness. Such a view still leaves unanswered the question why NREM dreams occur in the first place. The simplest answer would seem to be that NREM sleep is sufficiently similar to REM sleep to support dreaming, albeit dreaming that is more like waking mentation than is REM dreaming. This idea is consistent with the observation that a significant predictor of vividness is simply the level of energy metabolism in the cortex (Antrobus, 1991; Pivik, 1991).

Beyond this, it seems likely that the process of dream production is not centered in the brainstem, but in the forebrain. Solms (1999) has recently made such a suggestion, arguing that dreaming and REM sleep are distinct in terms of the brain processes that underlie them. He supports this contention with clinical studies that show no loss of dreaming following deep brainstem lesions (but see Hobson, Pace-Schott, and Stickgold, 2000), while dreaming is lost after certain cortical lesions even when brainstem initiated REM sleep is not disturbed (Solms, 1997).

In a similar vein, Foulkes (1999) argues that dreaming is characterized by high level cognitive processes and self-awareness. He maintains that this explains why dreams are rarely reported by infants or young children, though Hobson believes this to be an artifact of REM state amnesia (Hobson, Pace-Schott, and Stickgold, 2000).

The factors that could facilitate dreaming during SWS include a relaxation of waking constraints on cortical activity brought about during sleep by isolation from outside stimulation, the cessation of ordinary rational thought, and the sleep-associated neurochemical changes mentioned above. Such factors also include the presence of residual feelings and concerns from waking life.

All this must be animated by chaotic-like perturbation (see below) that allows cortical circuits to “relax” into the inherently comfortable but ever-changing attractor patterns that underlie the dream experience. Finally, some minimum level of arousal is necessary to sustain consciousness. It would seem from Tracy and Tracy’s (1974) findings, above, that this minimum level is lower than commonly thought.

We further note that during SWS higher brain functions are evidently isolated from external sensory input to a greater degree than is usually appreciated. This is evidenced, for example, by the general failure of sleep-learning studies to obtain positive results, even when using highly sensitive verbal priming techniques during light SWS (Wood, Bootzin, Kihlstrom, and Schacter, 1992). From this it would seem that the brain in SWS is sufficiently isolated from environmental stimulation to allow
This being the case, it would seem that the cortex is primed to flow from attractor to attractor even when not in REM sleep, though not as vigorouslyas when stimulated by PGO bombardment. Brain imaging studies need to be done that recognize the importance of SWS indreaming. Preliminary data, for instance, seems to indicate a complex relationship between REM and SWS in terms of frontallobe activation (Braun et al., 1998).

Hobson’s (1988, 1994) finding of neurochemical differences in the brain between REM, SWS, and wakefulness, suggests a greater elasticity in the REM dreaming than the waking brain, with SWS falling in between, as is consistent with dream content reports. It is not surprising, however, that REM dreams evidence greater emotional intensity than do those associated with SWS (Cavallero et al., 1992; Foulkes, 1992). As indicated above, brain imaging studies point to greater limbic system involvement in REM than in SWS sleep (Braun et al., 1998; Maquet et al., 1996), though specific comparisons of SWS dreaming and non-dream SWS, are not available.

All and all, it would seem that essentially the same dream facilitating factors are at play in SWS as in REM sleep. Nevertheless, the presence of PGO stimulation in the latter, along with greater limbic system involvement, as well as differences in neurochemical modulation and decreased frontal lobe activity, render the REM sleeping brain more favorable for dreaming. As suggested by Solms (1999), however, the best guess at this point is that dreaming and REM sleep are fundamentally oincidental.


Dream Content and Sensitivity to Subtle Influences


There are two important aspects of the behavior of complex systems such as the human brain during sleep that can make such systems sensitive to subtle influences. First, systems that reside in chaotic or near-chaotic states are subject to the butterfly effect (Kellert, 1993; Peak, 1994); very small alterations in the present state of a system can lead to surprisingly large variations in its future states. There seems little doubt that the human brain with its many chaotic and chaotic-like patterns of activity, is subject to the butterfly effect. Second, and more important, under certain circumstances the introduction of noise into such a system (chaotic or not) can cause the system to respond to signals too small to ordinarily be effected by them. Termed stochastic resonance, this seemingly paradoxical effect has been demonstrated in electronic circuits as well as in nerve cells (Moss and Wiesenfeld, 1995). It results from the fact that the presence of noise, or vibration, keeps the system in motion and following the signal, rather than allowing it to become stuck.

This is an active instance of the relaxing of a system that is exposed to vibration, as described above. For instance, objects on a vibrating tabletop are sometimes seen to “walk” about, especially if the table is not level. In fact, they are following the line of least resistance down the slope of the surface, ordinarily not available to them because of friction with the top of the table. Here, we might imagine that the arrival of PGO waves has a similar effect on the higher cortical regions of the brain during REM sleep, causing activity there to “slide” in the direction of least resistance.

In the dreaming brain, isolated from daytime sensory bombardment and detached by neuromodulatory amnesia fromthose experiences that immediately precede sleep, chaotic dynamics like the butterfly effect and stochastic resonance cause thebrain to become especially responsive to subtle influences such as faint residual memories or emotional residues. Writing of similar effects in connection networks, which indeed is a similar way to characterize dynamical systems such as the brain: Globus (1989) describes the following example, taken from Freud (1900/1953, p.169); Freud happens during the day to glance at a monograph on the plant Cyclamen in a bookstore window, a seeming indifferent impression that so commonly gets caught up in a dream. That night he dreams that he has written a monograph on a certain plant; the book lays open before him and at the moment he is turning over a folded cover plate.
(p.189)

Globus continues with this example, explaining that Cyclamen are Freud’s wife’s favorite flower (Freud reproaches himself for forgetting to buy her flowers), and beyond this, that he has himself once written a monograph on the coca plant, all of which places the momentary perception of the monograph on Cyclamen in a context of existing memories and feelings. The point, however, is that a fleeting perception, which leaves no deep impression, can later set off a chain of events in the dreaming rain though evidently to do so the perception must not occur immediately prior to sleep.

This example also points to the importance of feelings, even subtle feelings such as those elicited by the Freud’s association of the monograph with his wife’s favorite flower, and his wish to bring her flowers. As noted above, the importance of emotions in dreaming, especially REM sleep dreaming, is confirmed in the observations of heightened limbic system activity.

Given a dreaming brain that is amnesiac for short-term pre-sleep events, and at the same time responsive to subtle influences such as emotions and memories, it is not surprising that dream content frequently includes fragments of old memories and once-familiar feelings from the past (e.g., Domhoff, 1996; Hall and Van de Castle, 1966). In such a hyper-sensitive system other influences might occasionally be felt as well.

For example, Smith (1986) found among cardiac patients that the number of death references in men’s dreams, and separation references in women’s dreams, correlate with poor clinical outcomes, an aspects of human experience.

Conclusion

Bringing the above ideas together, the intent of this paper is to take a credible first step toward a reconciliation of brain-based (“process”) and content-based (“interpretative” or meaning oriented) approaches to understanding dreaming. Our discussion is based on the premise that the dreaming brain is a complex self-organizing system. Such systems can exhibit multifaceted adaptive properties that are, broadly speaking, “cognitive” in nature (e.g., Varela, Thompson, and Rosch, 1991). These arise through the interactions of their constitutive processes (Combs, 1996; Combs and Krippner, 1998; Goertzel, 1994, 2000; Kampis, 1991; Kauffman, 1993). In the case of the dreaming brain, these processes represent emotional, sensory, mnemonic, and other aspects of brain activity. Their ongoing readout into consciousness is the narrative experience of the dream.

Note, however, that we are not suggesting that a sufficient knowledge of such processes and their interactions would yield an explanation of the meaning of a particular dream in an individual’s conscious experience, or in the context of his or her life, at least not in the foreseeable future. Even if the regularities that underlie the neurological events of dreaming become well understood, they may still look quite different than those that best characterize the experiential aspects of dreaming (e.g., Haskell, 1986), which in turn set the stage for a dream’s meaning in the context of an individual’s life. Finding the precise relationships that connect the neurological to the experiential levels of dreaming is future work for cognitive neuropsychology.

Our aim here is to lay a foundation for this work by making explicit some of the important ways in which the dreaming brain engages in complex self-organizing processes which, far from random, are more than adequate in their regularity and complexity to support, at the level of consciousness, the experiential dream narratives that are the basis of interpretative approaches to dreaming.

References
Anderson, C.M. (1998). Ibogaine therapy in chemical dependency and posttraumatic stress disorder: A hypothesis involving the fractal nature of fetal REM sleep and interhemispheric reintegration. Multidisciplinary Association for Anderson, C.M., and Mandell, A.L. (1996). Fractal time and the foundations of consciousness: Vertical convergence of 1/f phenomena from ion channels to behavioral states. In M. Stamenov and G. Globus (Eds.), Fractals of brain, fractals of mind: In Search of a secret symmetry bond: Advances in consciousness research, 7 (pp. 75-126). Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Antrobus, J.S. (1990). Neurocognition of sleep mentation: Rapid eye movements, visual imagery, and dreaming. In R. Bootzin, J. Kihlstrom, and D. Schacter (Eds.), Sleep and cognition (pp. 3-24). Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.
Antrobus, J.S. (1991). Dreaming: Cognitive processes during cortical activation and high afferent thresholds. Psychological Review, 98, 96-121.
Antrobus, J.S., Hartwig, P., Rosa, D., Reisel, R., and Fein, G. (1987). Brightness and clarity of REM and NREM imagery:
Photo response scale. Sleep Research, 16, 240.
Arden, J.B. (1996). Consciousness, dreams, and self: A transdisciplinary approach. Madison, Connecticut: Psychosocial Press.
Arkin, A.M., Antrobus, J.S., and Ellman, S.J. (1978). The mind in sleep: Psychology and psychophysiology. Hillsdale, New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Basar, E. (Ed.). (1990). Chaos in brain function. Berlin: Springer Verlag.
Blagrove, M. (1996). Problems with the cognitive psychological modeling of dreaming. The Journal of Mind and
Behavior, 17, 99-134.
Bosinelli, M. (1995). Mind and consciousness during sleep. Behavioral Brain Research, 69, 195-201.
Braun, A.R., Balkin, T.J., Wesensten, N.J., Gwady, F., Carson, R.E., Varga, M., Baldwin, P., Belenky, G., and Herscovitch, P. (1998). Dissociated pattern of activity in visual cortices and their projections during human rapid eye movement
sleep. Science, 279, 91-95.
Cavallero, C., Cicogna, P., Natalie, V., Occhionero, M., and Zito, A. (1992). Slow wave sleep dreaming. Sleep, 15,
562-566.
Chalmers, D.J. (1995). The puzzle of conscious experience. Scientific American. 273, 80-86.
Clarke, E.H. (1878). Visions: a study of false sight (pseudopia). Boston: Houghton, Osgood.
Domhoff, G.W. (1996). Finding meaning in dreams: A quantitative approach. New York: Plenum.
Globus, G. (1989). Connectionism and the dreaming mind. The Journal of Mind and Behavior, 10, 179-196.
Combs, A. (1996). The radiance of being: Complexity, chaos, and the evolution of consciousness. St Paul,
Minnesota: Paragon House.
Combs, A., and Krippner S. (1998). Dream sleep and waking reality: A dynamical view of two states of consciousness. In
S. Hameroff, A.W. Kaszniak, and A.C. Scott (Eds.), Toward a science of consciousness: The second Tucson discussions
and debates (pp. 478-493). Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.
Crick, F., and Koch, C. (1995). Are we aware of neural activity in primary visual cortex? Nature, 375, 121-123.
Crick, F., and Michison, G. (1986). REM sleep and neural nets. The Journal of Mind and Behavior, 7, 229-250.
Dement, W., and Kleitman, N. (1957). The relation of eye movements during sleep to dream activity: An objective method
for the study of dreaming. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 53, 89-97.
Dement, W., Ferguson, J., Cohn, H., and Barchas, J. (1969). Non-chemical methods and data using a biochemical model:
The REM quanta. In A.J. Mandell and M.P. Mandall (Eds.), Psychochemical research in man (pp. 275-325). New York:
Academic Press.
Finkbeiner, A. K. (1998). The evolution of sleep. Science, 38, 17.
Fookson, J., and Antrobus, J. (1992). A connectionist model of bizarre thought. In J.S. Antrobus and M. Bertini (Eds.),
The neuropsychology of sleep and dreaming (197-214). Hillsdale, New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Foulkes, D. (1962). Dream reports from different stages of sleep. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 65,
14-25.
Foulkes, D. (1985). Dreaming: A cognitive-psychological analysis. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University
Press.
Foulkes, D. (1999). Children’s dreaming and the development of consciousness. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard
University Press.
Freeman, W.J, and Barrie, J.M. (1994). Chaotic oscillations and the genesis of meaning in cerebral cortex. In G. BuzÃÆ’Æ’¡ke,
R. LlinÃÆ’Æ’¡s, W. Singer. A. Berthoz, and Y. Christen (Eds.), Temporal coding in the brain (pp. 13-38). New York:
Springer-Verlag.
Freud, S. (1953). The interpretation of dreams. Standard edition, Vols. 4 and 5. [J. Strachey, Trans.] London: The
Hogarth Press. (Originally published in 1900.)
Goertzel, B. (1994). Chaotic logic. New York: Plenum.
Kampis, G. (1991). Self-modifying systems in biology and cognitive science. New York: Pergamon.
Goertzel, B. (2000). On the algebraic structure of consciousness. In A. Combs, M. Germine, and B. Goertzel. (Eds.).
Mind in time: The dynamics of thought, reality, and consciousness (27-40). Cresskill, New Jersey: Hampton.
Halaz, M.F. (1995). Nonlinear dynamics in behavioral systems. American Psychologist, 50, 109-405.
Hall, C.S., and Van de Castle, R.L. (1966). The content analysis of dreams. New York: Appletion-Century-Crofts.
Hardy, C. (1998). Networks of meaning: The bridge between mind and matter. Westport, Connecticut: Greenwood
Publishing.
Hartmann, E. (1966). The psychophysiology of free will. In R. Lowenstein, L. Newman, and A. Solnit (Eds.),
Psychoanalysis: A General Psychology (pp. 521-536). New York:International University Press.
Hartmann, E. (1999). Dreams and nightmares: The new theory on the origin and meaning of dreams. New York:
Plenum Press.
Herman, J. (1992). Transmutive and reproductive properties of dreams: Evidence for cortical modulation of brain stem
generators. In J. Antorbus and M. Bertini (Eds.), The neuropsychology of sleep and dreaming (pp. 260-273). Hillsdale,
New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Haskell, R.E. (1986). Cognitive psychology and dream research: Historical, conceptual, and epistemological
considerations. Journal of Mind and Behavior, 7, 131-160.
Hobson, J.A. (1988). The dreaming brain. New York: Basic Books.
Hobson, J.A. (1994). The chemistry of consciousness: How the brain changes its mind. New York: Little, Brown.
Hobson, J.A., and McCarley, R.W. (1977). The brain as a dream-state generator: An activation-synthesis hypothesis of
the dream process. American Journal of Psychiatry, 134, 1335-1368.
Hobson, J.A., Pace-Schott, E.F., and Stickgold, R. (2000, in press). Dreaming and the brain: Toward a cognitive
neuroscience of conscious states. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 23.
Hobson, J.A., Pace-Schott, E.F., Stickgold, R., and Kahn, D. (1998). To dream or not to dream? Relevant data from
new neuroimaging and electrophysiological studies. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 8, 239-244.
Hobson, J.A., and Steriade, M. (1986). The neural basis of behavioral state control. In F.E. Bloom (Ed.), Handbook of
physiologyÃÆ’¢â‚¬â€the nervous system, Vol. IV (297-338). American Psychological Society.
James, W. (1981). The principles of psychology. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press. (Originally
published 1890).
Jeong. J, Joung, M.K., and Kim., S.Y. (1988). Quantification of emotion by nonlinear analysis of the chaotic dynamics of
electroencephalograms during perception of 1/f music. Biological Cybernetics, 78, 217-225.
Jouvet, M. (1999). The paradox of sleep: The story of dreaming [L. Garey, Trans.]. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT
Press.
Kahn, D., Combs, A., and Krippner, S. (1998). The dreaming brain as a self-organizing system. In Consciousness
research abstracts: Toward a science of consciousness; Tucson III (p. 94). Thorverton, United Kingdom: Imprint
Academic.
Kahn, D., and Hobson, J.A. (1993). Self-organization theory of dreaming. Dreaming, 3, 151-178.
Kahn, D., Pace-Schott, E., and Hobson, J. (1997). Consciousness in the waking brain: The roles of neuronal oscillation
and neuromodulation in determining similarities and differences. Neuroscience, 78, 13-38.
Kampis, G. (1991). Self- modifying systems in biology and cognitive science. New York: Pergamon.
Kauffman, S.A. (1993). The origins of order: Self-organization and selection in evolution. New York, Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Kellert, S.H. (1993). In the wake of chaos: Unpredictable order in dynamical systems. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Koch. C. (1998). Visual awareness and the frontal lobes. In Consciousness research abstracts: Toward a science of
consciousness; Tucson III (p. 80). Thorverton, United Kingdom: Imprint Academic.
Krippner, S. (1991). An experimental approach to the anomalous dream. In J. Gackenbach and A.A. Sheikh (Eds.),
Dream images: A call to mental arms (pp. 31-54). Amityville, New York: Baywood Publishing.
Mamelak, A.N., and Hobson, J.A. (1989). Dream bizarreness as the cognitive correlate of altered neuronal behavior in
REM sleep. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience. 1, 201-222.
Maquet, P., Peters, J.M., Aerts, J., Delfiore, G., Degueldre, C., Luxen, A., and Franck, G. (1996). Functional
neuroanatomy of human rapid-eye-movement sleep and dreaming. Nature, 383, 163-166.
Moffitt, A. (1995). Dreaming: Functions and meanings. Impulse, 3, 18-31.
Moss, F., and Wiesenfeld, K. (1995). The benefits of background noise. Scientific American. 272, 66-69.
Mountcastle, V.B. (1974). Sleep, wakefulness, and the conscious state: Intrinsic regulatory mechanisms of the brain. In
V.B. Mountcastle (Ed.), Medical physiology: Thirteenth edition (pp. 254-281). Saint Louis: Mosby.
Nielsen, T.A. (1999). Mentation during sleep: The NREM/REM distinction. In R. Lydic and H.A. Baghdoyan (Eds.),
Handbook of behavioral state control: Molecular and cellular mechanisms (pp. 101-128). Boca Raton, Florida: CRC
Press.
Peak, D. (1994). Chaos under control: The art and science of complexity. New York: W.H. Freeman.
Pivik, R.T. (1991). Tonic states and phasic events in relation to sleep mentation. In S.J. Ellman, and J.S. Antrobus (Eds.),
The mind in sleep (pp. 378-406). New York: John Wiley Sons.
Port, R.F., and van Gelder, T. (1995). Mind as motion: Explorations in the dynamics of cognition. Cambridge,
Massachusetts: MIT Press.
Porte, H,, and Hobson, J.A. (1986). Bizarreness in REM and SWS reports. Sleep Research, 15, 81.
Pribram, K.H. (Ed.). (1995). Proceedings of the Second Appalachian Conference on Behavioral Neurodynamics:
Origins; Brain and Self-Organization. Hillsdale, New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Revonsuo, A. (1998). How to take consciousness seriously in cognitive neuroscience. In Consciousness research
abstracts: Toward a science of consciousness; Tucson III (p. 76). Thorverton, United Kingdom: Imprint Academic.
Robertson, R., and Combs, A. (Eds.). (1995). The proceedings of the society for chaos theory in psychology and the life
sciences. Hillsdale, New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Roschke, J., and Aldenhoff, J.B. (1992). A nonlinear approach to brain function: Deterministic chaos and sleep EEG.
Sleep, 15, 95-101.
Roschke, J., and Aldenhoff, J.B. (1991). The dimensionality of human’s electroencephalogram during sleep. Biological
Cybernetics, 64, 307-313.
Russell, C., Bruck. D., and Coleman, G. (1997). Induction of visual imagery during SWS. Sleep, 20, 948-956.
Screenivason, R., Pradhan, N., and Rapp, P. (Eds.). (1999). Nonlinear dynamics and brain functioning. Huntington, New
York: Nova Science.
Smith, R.C. (1986). Evaluating dream function: Emphasizing the study of patients with organic disease. The Journal of
Mind and Behavior, 7, 397-410.
Solms, M. (1997). The neuropsychology of dreams: A clinico-anatomical study. Mahwah, New Jersey: Lawrence
Erlbaum.
Solms, M. (1999, January). Dreaming and REM sleep are controlled by different brain mechanisms. Paper presented at
the Annual Meeting of the American Association for the Advancement of Science, Anaheim, California.
Steriade, M., and McCormic, D.A. (1990). Brainstem control of wakefulness and sleep. New York: Plenum.
Tonay, V. (1991). California women and their dreams: A historical and sub-cultural comparison of dream content.
Imagination-Cognition-and-Personality, 10, 85-99.
Tracy, R.L., and Tracy, L.N. (1974). Reports of mental activity from sleep stages 2 and 4. Perceptual and Motor Skills,
38, 647-648.
Tschacher, W., and Dauwalder, J.P. (Eds.). (1999). Dynamics, synergetics, autonomous agents: Nonlinear systems
approaches to cognitive psychology and cognitive science. Singapore: World Scientific.
Ullman, M. (1999). Dreaming consciousness and quantum concepts: Suggestive correlations. Journal of Scientific
Exploration, 13, 91-112.
Varela, F.J., Thompson, E., and Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience.
Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.
Vogel, G.W. (1978). An alternative view of the neurobiology of dreaming. American Journal of Psychiatry, 135,
1531-1535.
Wood, J.M., Bootzin, R.R., Kihlstrom, J.F., and Schacter, D.L. (1992). Implicit and explicit memory for verbal
information presented during sleep. Psychological Science, 3, 236-239.